Oets Kolk Bouwsma

Oets Kolk Bouwsma
Bouwsma in his later years
BornNovember 22, 1898
DiedMarch 1, 1978(1978-03-01) (aged 79)
EducationCalvin College, University of Michigan
Era20th-century philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
SchoolAnalytic philosophy
InstitutionsUniversity of Nebraska
Main interests
Philosophy of language, epistemology, Christian existentialism

Oets Kolk Bouwsma (November 22, 1898 – March 1, 1978) was an American analytic philosopher.

Education and early career

[edit]

O. K. Bouwsma (as he was usually known)[1] was born on November 22, 1898 in Muskegon, Michigan,[2] to Dutch-born Americans Joachum Everts Bouswma and Hillegian Kolk Bouwsma.[3][4] His parents maintained close ties to the Netherlands and the Dutch-American communities of western Michigan.[5] Bouwsma was raised within the Protestant ethic of the Dutch Reformed Church,[1] with Dutch as the language of biblical reading and mealtime prayers.[3]

Bouwsma attended Calvin College (1916– 1919) serving, during World War I, as a member of the Student Army Training Corps.[4] From the University of Michigan, he obtained an AB in 1920, MA in 1922, and, with a dissertation "On Difference in the Criterion of F. H. Bradley", his PhD in 1928. While a graduate student, Bouwsma worked as an Instructor in English at the university (1922-1928). He was appointed Assistant Professor at the University of Nebraska in 1928, where he was promoted to Associate Professor and then Professor of Philosophy, remaining on the faculty until his retirement.[2][4]

In his early years he was an advocate of idealism but later found the work of G. E. Moore's common sense counters to skepticism more appealing. Nonetheless, he was critical of Moore. He developed his own technique of analysis that focused on uncovering hidden analogies driving Moore's ways of speaking about sense data. He worked intensely on Moore, publishing a significant paper, "Moore’s Theory of Sense-Data", which was included in the Library of Living Philosophers volume on Moore. The essay reflected the beginnings of a method of philosophical analysis that was soon to be forged by his reading of Ludwig Wittgenstein.

Later career

[edit]

With a fine ear for expression, Bouwsma fastened on poetry, James Joyce’s Ulysses and Finnegans Wake, Shakespeare, Dickens, and novelists who artistically capture the expressions of ordinary language. In this regard he reflected often on the writing and reading of literature. He wrote and lectured on the “truth” of poetry, emphasizing its aesthetic value as opposed to its moral value. He also wrote on the puzzling relationship of words to music in “The Expression Theory of Art.” Extensive marginal notes filling his copies of Ulysses and Finnegans Wake indicate how consumed he was by Joyce's word play and how he appropriated a sensitivity to word play in his own writing style.

Engaged in Moore's philosophy, Bouwsma sent students from the University of Nebraska, most notably Morris Lazerowitz, to study with Moore at Cambridge. Lazerowitz's wife Alice Ambrose, a student of Wittgenstein as well as Moore, introduced Bouwsma to Wittgenstein's revolutionary ideas in The Blue Book. Norman Malcolm, another of Bouwsma's students, became a prominent interpreter and presenter of Wittgenstein's ideas in America, after studying with Wittgenstein at Cambridge. Malcolm, who later taught at Cornell, was able to persuade Wittgenstein to visit there. Simultaneously, Malcolm arranged for Bouwsma to teach at Cornell during Wittgenstein's visit. By that time, in 1949, Bouwsma had absorbed the implications of Wittgenstein's philosophy in The Blue Book. With a leave from the University of Nebraska and a Fulbright Fellowship, he was able to spend much of the next two years discussing philosophy with Wittgenstein at Cornell, Smith College, and Oxford. Through Wittgenstein, Bouwsma developed an understanding of what he had been groping for in his work on Moore.

After the personal influence of Wittgenstein and much hard work on The Blue Book and Philosophical Investigations, Bouwsma emerged with a unique method of philosophical analysis that he applied to a variety of philosophical problems. He continued to attack the skepticism of Descartes that reflected the idealism from which Bouwsma fought to free himself. Applying Wittgenstein's radical turn of displaying the nonsense in place of refuting a philosophical theory, he turned to Berkeley's idealism where he teased the failure to make sense of ideas as entities in the mind out into the open. With a focus on the opening question of The Blue Book on meaning, he wrote tirelessly on the idea of "meaning as use," until he shook himself loose of the notion that Wittgenstein was presenting another philosophical theory of meaning. He came to understand and appropriate the idea that Wittgenstein had developed a set of techniques to arm the philosopher in the struggle against the “bewitchment of his intelligence by means of language.” This understanding culminated in Bouwsma's accomplished article, The Blue Book, which described the aims of the new method of philosophical analysis. With such perennial conceptually puzzling concepts as “time,” “truth,” and “thinking,” he carefully and often humorously compared sentences of philosophers with actual sentences of daily life – earning Bouwsma a notable place in what came to be called “ordinary language philosophy.” With this reputation, Gilbert Ryle asked Bouwsma to deliver the first of the famous John Locke Lectures at Oxford University.

With a lifelong attachment to the Christian Reformed Church, Bouwsma philosophically engaged the concepts of Christianity. Applying his acquired techniques of philosophical analysis, he carefully distinguished the uses of the word “belief” in religious settings from uses in non-religious settings. When called upon in philosophy to illuminate puzzling Christian concepts, he drew on his lifelong participation in the community of faith and on his reading of the Scriptures to dramatically bring to life their meaning. In addition to Wittgenstein, his work on Kierkegaard was the other great influence in Bouwsma's philosophical development. He came to understand the significance of Kierkegaard’s concept of “subjectivity” for thinking philosophically about Christianity. On the one hand, “subjectivity” points to understanding the language of religion in the context of particular religious communities – an idea parallel to Wittgenstein's idea of understanding words and sentences in language-games and forms of life. On the other hand, “subjectivity” makes clear that Christianity is an invitation to new life and not an objective system of metaphysics. His papers in the philosophy of religion are collected separately in a volume with the title, Without Proof or Evidence, published by the University of Nebraska Press.

With a fine ear for expression, Bouwsma fastened on poetry, James Joyce’s Ulysses and Finnegans Wake, Shakespeare, Dickens, and novelists who artistically capture the expressions of ordinary language. In this regard he reflected often on the writing and reading of literature. He wrote and lectured on the “truth” of poetry, emphasizing its aesthetic value as opposed to its moral value. He also wrote on the puzzling relationship of words to music in “The Expression Theory of Art.” Extensive marginal notes filling his copies of Ulysses and Finnegans Wake indicate how consumed he was by Joyce's word play and how he appropriated a sensitivity to word play in his own writing style.

Bouwsma was President of the Western Division of the American Philosophical Association from 1957-58.[6]

Bouwsma taught philosophy at the University of Nebraska from 1928 until 1965 and the University of Texas from 1965 until 1977. His greatest influence came, not so much through his humorously and finely written essays, but thrgh the many graduate students he trained in his unique style of exploring the borderlands of sense and nonsense in philosophical sentences. Although he wrote incessantly and presented numerous papers, he published only one book toward the end of his career – a collection of essays titled Philosophical Essays. He died in 1978 in Austin, Texas.[7] His papers and daily notebooks, the latter filling hundreds of legal pads, are housed in the Harry Ransom Humanities Research Center at The University of Texas, Austin. J.L. Craft and Ronald E. Hustwit Sr. co-edited and published two additional volumes of his papers and selections of his commonplace book. His notebooks recording his discussions with Wittgenstein, published with the title, Wittgenstein Conversations, 1949-51, have become a primary source for Wittgenstein studies.

Publications

[edit]

Books

[edit]

The following works, collected and edited by J.L. Craft and R.E. Hustwit Sr., were published posthumously:

Select papers and book chapters

[edit]

For more complete publication details see Annotated Bibliography on O.K. Bouwsma Collection (2009) by Ronald E. Hustwit Sr.

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ a b Rozema, David (2017). "Ronald E.Hustwit, K. Bouwsma: A Philosopher's Journey (New York: Peter Lang, 2015). x + 228 pages, price £53.00 hb". Philosophical Investigations. 40 (1): 93–94. doi:10.1111/phin.12140. ISSN 0190-0536.
  2. ^ a b Jolley, Kelly Dean (2005). "Bouwsma, Oets Kolk (1898–1978)". In Shook, John R. (ed.). The dictionary of modern American philosophers. Bristol: Thoemmes. pp. 298–299. ISBN 978-1-84371-037-0.
  3. ^ a b Hustwit, Ronald E. (2014). "A sketch of a journey". O. K. Bouwsma: a philosopher's journey. American university studies Ser. 5, Philosophy. New York Bern Frankfurt Berlin Vienna: Lang. pp. 1–2. ISBN 978-1-4331-2576-8.
  4. ^ a b c Hull, Richard T. (2013), "Biography: Oets Kolk Bouwsma:", American Philosophical Association Centennial Series, Philosophy Documentation Center, p. 391, doi:10.5840/apapa2013466, retrieved 2024-12-02
  5. ^ Hustwit, Ronald E. (1992). "A Sketch of O. K. Bouwsma's Academic Life". Something about O. K. Bouwsma. Lanham : University Press of America. pp. ix.
  6. ^ Shook, John R., ed. (2016). The Bloomsbury Encyclopedia of Philosophers in America From 1600 to the Present. Bloomsbury Publishing. p. 107.
  7. ^ "Bouwsma, O.K." University of Nebraska Archives.
  8. ^ Holland, R. F. (1966). "Review of Philosophical Essays". Philosophy. 41 (156): 186–188. doi:10.1017/S0031819100058605. ISSN 0031-8191 – via JSTOR.
  9. ^ Winch, Peter (June 1985). "O. K. Bouwsma. Without Proof or Evidence, essays edited and introduced by J. L. Craft and Ronald E. Hustwit. (Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press1984.) Pp. xiv + 161. £ 17.05". Religious Studies. 21 (2): 260–263. doi:10.1017/S0034412500017303. ISSN 0034-4125.
  10. ^ Inwagen, Peter van (1987). "Without Proof or Evidence: Essays of O. K. Bouwsma". Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers. 4 (1): 103–108. doi:10.5840/faithphil19874110. ISSN 0739-7046.
  11. ^ Hunter, J. F. M. (1985). "O.K. Bouwsma, "Without Proof or Evidence."". Philosophy in Review. 5 (2): 49–52. ISSN 1920-8936 – via Internet Archive.
  12. ^ Szabados, Béla (1987). "Wittgenstein: Conversations 1949–1951, O. K. Bowsma Edited by J. L. Craft and Ronald E. Hustwit Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1986. Pp. xxiv, 78". Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review. 26 (4): 771–773. doi:10.1017/S0012217300018436. ISSN 0012-2173.
  13. ^ Black, Tim (1999). "Bouwsma's Notes on Wittgenstein's Philosophy, 1965-1975, J. L. Craft and Ronald Hustwit, editors. Lewiston, NY: The Edwin Mellen Press, 1996." Reason Papers 24:131-138.
  14. ^ Rozema, David (2003). "Review of O. K. Bouwsma's Commonplace Book: Remarks on Philosophy and Education". Philosophical Investigations. 26 (4): 369–374. doi:10.1111/1467-9205.00209. ISSN 0190-0536 – via Academia.edu.

Further reading

[edit]
[edit]
  • O.K. Bouwsma Collection – selections taken from the Bouwsma collection at the Harry Ransome Center at the University of Texas in Austin, gathered, edited and accompanied by an introduction by Ronald E. Hustwit Sr.